Opinion
In discussing the U.S. v. Rahimi case at oral argument, SCOTUS (Supreme Court of the United States) justices seem to be wrestling with the concept of “dangerous.” More specifically, does it pass constitutional muster to strip someone of his RKBA because the person is alleged to be “dangerous”?
What is “dangerous”? How may that be evaluated? Should that be applied to deprivation of a fundamental constitutional right?
Definitions. First, Let Us Look At Some Definitions.
A. Blacks Law Dictionary, Fifth Edition
Dangerous. Attended with risk; perilous; hazardous; unsafe. See also Danger.
Danger. Jeopardy; exposure to loss or injury; peril …
Dangerous instrumentality. Anything which has the inherent capacity to place people in peril, either in itself (e.g. dynamite), or by careless use of it (e.g. boat). (Citation omitted) Due care must be exercised in using to avoid injury to those reasonably expected to be in proximity. …
Dangerous per se. A thing that may inflict injury without the immediate application of human aid or instrumentality.
Dangerous weapon. One dangerous to life; one by the use of which a fatal wound may probably or possible be given. As the manner of use enters into the consideration as well as other circumstances, the question is often one of fact for the jury, but not infrequently one of law for the court.
B. Dictionary.com
Dangerous – adjective
-
- full of danger or risk; causing danger; perilous; risky; hazardous; unsafe.
- able or likely to cause physical injury; a dangerous criminal.
C. Merriam-Webster online
Dangerous – adjective
-
- exposing to or involving danger
- able or likely to inflict injury or harm.
D. Cambridge Dictionaries online
Dangerous – adjective
-
- describes a person, animal or activity that could harm you
Evaluation of Dangerous Definitions
The word “dangerous” is accepted by all sources as an adjective;
…”a word that describes a noun or pronoun.” It may be presumed that all instances of “dangerous” in the Heller decision are used to describe or elucidate another object, usually “weapons,” always some type of firearms, sometimes machine guns and sometimes handguns. In Rahimi, the term “dangerous” is used in reference to people.
Dangerous.
- The terms “dangerous” or “danger” submit to analysis and several deducible rules worth identifying before proceeding with this discussion:
- Rule # 1. Anything can be dangerous, given the necessary conditions. Sunlight can be dangerous to people in too long or too strong a dose. The ultraviolet portion of sunlight is immediately lethal (very dangerous) to some microorganisms. Air can be dangerous to people under very high pressure (e.g. high pressure air used to cut solid materials), if air is injected into a person’s vein or if air is simply absent. Knowledge can be dangerous if used wrongly. Raccoons can be dangerous if cornered. The list is endless…
- Rule # 2. Nothing is always dangerous. A compound that is lethal in war may grow more food in peacetime as fertilizer or pesticide. Extreme cold, that may be devastating as weather may also be essential for scientific experiments or industrial processes.
- Rule # 3. Whether or not something is dangerous depends entirely upon prevailing conditions. Water, although essential for normal life, is one of the leading causes of human death in the U.S.
- Rule # 4. Danger requires an affected or potentially affected object. For something to be dangerous, it must create a risk to a person, an animal, or something else, such as “wolves are dangerous to elk” or “socialism is dangerous to democracy.” Without an object, it is impossible to sustain the argument that anything is dangerous. “Dangerous weather,” for example, might be dangerous to crops or pilots. A “dangerous calculation” might endanger the resolution of a formula. There must be some apparent or implied object at risk to validate the concept of danger.
- Rule # 5. Danger itself is not an object – a “thing” – but is a condition or a subjective descriptor of a thing, an activity, or a process – a perception.
- Rule # 6. Danger is not absolute but is, according to the eye of the beholder – a matter of opinion. One person may think spiders are dangerous, another not. One may think sky-diving is dangerous, another not.
- Rule # 7. Since danger is in the eye of the beholder, danger may be perceived but not real (a person afraid of a non-venomous snake), and danger may be real but not perceived (a person living happily on the slope of an active volcano).
- Rule # 8. The level of actual danger is a combination of risk and stake. If a person bets a penny on the lottery, there is no serious danger even though the risk is high because the stake is low. Increase the stake to $1,000, and the actual danger becomes greater. Decrease the risk (e.g., only ten lottery ticket buyers), and the danger becomes less. This rule may be stated as “Risk X Stake = Level of Danger.”
- Dangerous generally includes things that are actively dangerous, such as a “dangerous stunt,” and things that are potentially dangerous, such as “dangerous terrain.”
- Potentially dangerous things are things that can not be dangerous without active instrumentality, such as a “dangerous cliff” or a “dangerous idea.” See “Dangerous per se” above. Potentially dangerous things are not actually dangerous without some activation.
- Actively dangerous things are dangerous because of some intervention, application, or instrumentality, such as “dangerous driving.”
Deprivation of Rights
For a person to be deprived of a constitutional right by the state, it would seem that a person must be actively dangerous and not passively dangerous. There must be an actual threat involved. That is, the person must not only be dangerous but must also be actually threatening someone else.
Consider, for example, a person who is adept with firearms, possesses one or more of them, and has a firm opinion about not being a victim of violence. Therefore, this person is arguably dangerous but not actively so. This person is probably actively dangerous to armed home invaders or a large predator attacking his dog but otherwise makes no threats. Thus, the necessary combination of dangerous and threatening has not been satisfied for this person. This person is not subject to state restriction.
Alternately, imagine a three-year-old child denied a treat and having a temper tantrum. The child is pounding on the kneecaps of an adult with closed fists and verbally promising mayhem. This child is clearly threatening but is not dangerous to the adult. In this example, the necessary combination of dangerous and threatening has not been satisfied, so no state restriction is allowed here either.
Conclusion
“Dangerous” and “dangerousness” are fuzzy concepts – highly subjective at best.
Fuzzy and subjective concepts are inappropriate measures when considering the deprivation of rights. Then, consider a person armed with a firearm or with a quart glass jar full of gasoline. Both are arguably dangerous, but neither has demonstrated any threat to anyone or anything else.
Before the state may take the extreme step of depriving a person of a fundamental and constitutional right, that person should be proven by some process to be both dangerous and threatening – both! The “some process” may be the rub in the Rahimi case. Enter “due process,” which, unfortunately, is not an issue in the Rahimi case.
Federal law can currently make it a felony for a person to possess firearms (strip a person of a fundamental right) – this because a state court denied that person the right without due process or because a state court issued a restraining order against a person even without actively restricting firearm possession, again without due process. Thus, there is too often no procedurally protected process for determining that a person is both dangerous and threatening before effectively stripping the person of his or her RKBA.
This is where the status quo of the interactive effect of federal and state laws crosses the constitutional double-yellow and clearly needs repair from SCOTUS. The Rahimi case may be the right vehicle for that, but the Range case is also pending to possibly get even more directly at this problem.
Any SCOTUS conclusion that fails to utilize both danger and threat and due process to determine those will not properly resolve the issues at hand in Rahimi.
All of this is in addition to SCOTUS’s consideration of whether or not RKBA-depriving laws in the domestic relations sphere meet the text, history, and tradition standard for constitutional permissibility that SCOTUS established in the Bruen case.
Gary Marbut is the author of Gun Laws of Montana and is president of the Montana Shooting Sports Association, the primary political advocate for Montana gun owners.
Most of the life forms on this planet move out of our way. Some of them even run in panic from our very scent.
Why?
Because they know something some of us don’t. We’re all dangerous. Especially in groups. We’ve created various behaviors, societal norms, and laws in an attempt to control that dangerousness among ourselves. Some of us follow those rules better than others, often depending on circumstances.
But we’re all dangerous.
Marbut is needed as a regular contributor here. It’s the details that matter and this deep analysis of one small aspect is edifying. It does leave me wondering when a firearm crosses over the threshold from “potentially dangerous” to ‘instrumentally dangerous.’ Round in the chamber? Round(s) in an inserted magazine? … Firearm un-lockable and ammunition in the vicinity?
Legislators routinely avoid the specific in drafting legislation because they find comfort in the general and the non-specific. In order to avoid stepping on toes they can try to satisfy all sides of a policy debate by leaving terms nebulous and kicking the can of specifics down the road to the courts. This condition exists for two reasons: first, we are an ideologically and philosophically divided society. We hold no truths to be self evident. That being said, drafting any legislation that does not offend some substantial minority is nearly impossible. Catering to vocal minority groups is a way of… Read more »
I am not opposed to the death penalty on moral grounds – I believe that for some crimes, death is a just sentence. However, I do oppose it on pragmatic grounds – the government has proven that it is incompetent to implement the death penalty in a timely, just, and cost-effective manner, and too may folks have been put to death only to be exonerated after the fact. I would much rather not put to death those who may deserve it, than to even once put to death someone who does not. I view the issue outlined in this article… Read more »
The founders rejected the idea of limiting the 2A to “peaceable” citizens. The first proposal for what became the 2A (and various other parts of the Bill of Rights) had such a provision. It was dropped in all subsequent proposals because people knew stateists like like Clinton would use it to justify disarming everyone from Private Martin to General Washington.
I love this article. Right now the left is pushing that Donald Trump is dangerous and an existential threat to the WORLD and the planet and that anyone that supports him, especially MAGA supporters are dangerous. Funny that whoever it is that is talking has their own definition of what they interpret dangerous to be!!! There is no standard of what it is, it is what they think it is and it is all based on how they FEEL. BS I use Merriam Webster for my definitions, college edition. It’s about 4 inches thick and fortunately it doesn’t have shit… Read more »